Gregory, a bishop of Nyssa in 371, was part of the Cappadocian trio, and was instrumental in the development of Trinitarian orthodoxy. His theological prowess proved vital in response to the Arian and Sabellian heresies. Key to Gregory’s theology we find “an emergence of a pro-Nicene ‘grammar’ of divinity through his developed account of divine power,”[1] conceived through a nature-power-activity formulation revealed in the created order and articulated in Scripture. Understanding the Triune God in this manner afforded a conception of the Trinity that was logical and thoroughly biblical. And this letter is paradigmatic on Gregory’s account of the divine nature. (*This article was later published with Credo Magazine, titled, “The Grammar of Divinity (On Theology).” See link below)
To Ablabius, though short, is a polemical address whereby Gregory lays out a complex argument in response to the claim that three Divine Persons equal three gods. Basically put, Ablabius (his opponent, to whom the letter is addressed) charges Gregory with teaching that there are “three Gods.” It is an objection that many of us might have thought about or maybe have had to explain to others, even a Jehovah’s Witness. Gregory’s Trinitarian (Eastern) theology differs from the Western view, most notably in its monarchial form,[2] which was consistent with many of the early church fathers. The Eastern view posited that in order to affirm One God, there has to be One God. And, as that one God—the Father, which Scripture and the early creeds of the church affirm, is the source from which the Son and the Spirit come.[3] We moderns see such language and think Gregory is drifting away from a Trinitarian doctrine. However, that is not the case. The Son and the Spirit are of the same nature as the Father. According to Gregory, when the divine persons are referenced together in the NT, we see an order in the Godhead: the One God, the Father and One Lord, Jesus Christ (e.g., 1 Cor 8:6). For Gregory, what classifies all three to be of the same nature is their power and activity as manifested in creation and Scripture. And this letter details Gregory’s development of this argument in order to demonstrate that we believe in One God, not three Gods.
The crucial issue in the debate concerns the grammar of divinity. Lewis Ayres points out that “the fourth century controversies are, in part, easily misunderstood if they are conceived as concentrating on the question ‘is the Son (and the Spirit) divine?’”[4] It was understood that the Father was the arche, the Source, from which the Son and the Spirit come. The challenge, then, was in accepting that the Son was truly the same nature as the Father. The divine essence was understood to be simple and inseparable. Therefore, to affirm “real” distinction in the divine essence, where the persons exist as individual hypostases was problematic.[5] As noted, it is the grammar of divinity that needs developing. Gregory’s approach marks a broad shift in pro-Nicene theology in its discussion of the Son being homoousios with the Father, sharing the divine essence, while both the Son and Spirit coming from the Father and acting in creation.[6]
On the surface, Ablabius’ charge seems valid. How is our belief in a Triune God consistent with monotheism? Gregory begins his letter by stating Ablabius’ argument, which goes like this:
Gregory is very forthright about the difficulty of this issue. We have a language problem. We enumerate the Divine Persons but do not admit the plurality, as we would Peter, James, and John. We would say they have the same nature as humans, but we designate them as distinct beings from each other. Thus, we have three men; whereas, when it comes to Persons of the Godhead each having the divine nature, we do not have three Gods. Gregory delineates this further. When we speak of men, we say Luke is a man or Stephen is a man, but we don’t say Stephen is Luke or Luke is Stephen. There’s a separation of persons—beings, though having the common nature of man they are considered separate from each other. “Man” isn’t proper to Luke; it is common to him, as it is to Stephen, and any other man that has lived, lives, or will live. The nature of man is inseparable, not capable of increase or decrease. Although it appears in a plurality, it is nevertheless complete and not divided with the individuals—Stephen and Luke—who participate in it.
Gregory points out that the challenge is in the manner of how we speak about people. We refer to groups (people, army, or a mob) in the singular. Though understood to be a plurality, “man” is still considered one, even though the one nature of “man” is exhibited to us as a plurality. As it pertains to God, we have to confess that God is One according to Scripture (Deut 6:4) though the name “Godhead” extends through the Holy Trinity. The disparity lies in that we know it is improper, “in the case of human nature, . . to extend the name of the nature by the mark of plurality” (Ad Abl., 332). Even though an army is made up of a plurality, the human nature is only one; it is not multiplied. Thus, with God, it is improper for us to associate the name Godhead with the divine nature because, as Scripture teaches us, the divine nature is “unnameable and unspeakable.” So, whatever name we use to speak of the divine nature, such names cannot signify the nature itself. What does Gregory mean by that?
Gregory writes:
We do not perceive divinity directly. Rather, we do so by a process of what Gregory calls epinoia, or the process of abstracting conceptions or reflecting on the things about God, based upon what he has revealed to us in creation and Scripture—which provides us a guiding grammar to speak analogously, though truthfully, about God. However, we maintain the understanding that we cannot know God in the truest sense. Somehow, we can “touch” God; however, he always remains unknown.[7] Gregory says this process of epinoia is continual. Elsewhere he writes, “But in applying such appellations to the Divine essence, ‘which passeth all understanding,’ we do not seek to glory in it by the names we employ, but to guide our own selves by the aid of such terms towards the comprehension of the things which are hidden” (Cont. Eun. 13, 265).[8]
Gregory notes that we use the name “Godhead” to describe God’s activity (his nature is unknown to us), as watching over us, seeing, or beholding. The Three Persons are ascribed each of these activities in Scripture. In Psalm 84:9, David says, of the Father, “See, O God our defender,” in which sight is a proper operation of God. In Matthew 9:4, Jesus sees the thoughts of those who condemn him, questioning his power to pardon sinners. And the classic passage of Ananias and Saphira lying to Peter (Acts 5:3), in which the Holy Spirit is the true witness of this act, in that he was aware of their secret actions, sharing with Peter what he observed (Ad Abl., 333). In Gregory’s analyses of the term “Godhead,” whereby each member of the Trinity is engaged in the same activity of seeing, he concludes that “if the activities are the same, then the power which gave rise to them is the same and the ineffable divine nature in which that power is inherent must also be one.”[9]
But Gregory admits that his argument is not satisfactory. The “three Gods” claim still has relevance because mankind, having the same nature, does the same things proper to humanity, which are appropriately spoken of as three (e.g., three orators; three shoemakers). Understanding this issue, Gregory moves on to bring the apparent contradiction to a close. As it pertains to the common example of humanity, we understand that each of those activities are done by separate individuals, “according to the special character of [each one’s] operation.” And therefore, Gregory writes, these “pursuits” would be considered many. However, as it pertains to the divine nature, Gregory writes,
Gregory is illuminating to us that the Trinity has an order, from which the divine activity (energia) of the Three Persons, is one motion, communicated from the Father, through the Son, and to the Spirit. The divine nature is unknown, but we see the divine operations carried out by one power, leading to a conception of an undivided Godhead. Gregory deploys a helpful phrase from nature, which speaks of the power and action of God “issuing from the Father as from a spring, brought into operation by the Son, and perfecting its grace by the power of the Spirit” (Ad Abl., 334). In phrasing his understanding of God’s divine activity, demonstrating his power and character, Gregory addresses the “Three Gods” problem, in that God’s activity is not individuated as we would see in human natures. God’s activity as observed in creation and narrated in Scripture, reveals One power, which always works without delay according to the motion of the Divine will “by a unitary causal sequenced activity of the three persons.”[10]
“Godhead” is a name. It is an appellation given to the unlimited and incomprehensible Divine nature. Gregory notes “that the Deity is above every name: and ‘Godhead’ is a name” (Ad Abl., 335). In revisiting the error—applying the name of a nature to denote a multitude—Gregory emphasizes the point that Scripture never speaks of God as Gods. Nature is indivisible; however, Gregory writes, Scripture names “men” in the plural “because no one is by a figure of speech led astray in his conceptions to imagine a multitude of humanities or supposes that many human natures are indicated by the fact that the name expressive of nature is used in the plural” (Ad Abl., 336). As it pertains to Scripture’s reference to God: “The Father is God: the Son is God: and yet by the same proclamation God is One, because no difference either of nature or of operation is contemplated in the Godhead.” The Lord our God is One Lord, with Scripture declaring the Only-begotten Son as God from the Father, but we do not have two Gods. The reason for our proclamation that God is One, Gregory writes, is because “no difference either of nature or of operation is contemplated in the Godhead.” Ayres succinctly puts it: “The sequence of the one divine action ad extra reflects the nature and order of God’s internal generation, and in both the same sequence of causality is operative.”[11]
As he comes to a close in his letter to Ablabius, Gregory addresses the matter of the distinction of Persons. The matter looms overhead because of the human (weakness?) understanding of individuation. The Persons are distinguished from each other: One, the Father, is the without Cause; the Only-begotten is directly from the First Cause, with the Spirit proceeding from the Father through the Son. Gregory notes,
His point is that generation presents the mode of existence; but what exists is not indicated by the phrase generation. The phrase begotten, as applied to the Son, teaches us the mode of his existence and how we are to conceive of him, but it does not tell us what he is. And in recognizing as such, the grammar of divinity, allows us to acknowledge a distinction in the Trinity, whereby One is the Cause, and another is of the Cause, and thus “we can no longer be accused of confounding the definition of the Persons by the community of nature” (Ad Abl., 336).
And Gregory concludes his letter to Ablabius:
Gregory set out to delineate a Trinitarian doctrine that was logical yet derived from Holy Scripture. His dynamic line of argumentation, whereby the energeia—the activity and power of God as observed in a causal “from–through–in” order by each of the Persons, cogently and coherently articulated a monarchial formula of divine power and activity from God the Father, mediated through the Only Begotten Son, and in the Spirit. The Triune God, therefore, is not Tri-deity.
—Romans 11:36
*https://credomag.com/article/the-grammar-of-divinity-on-theology/.
_________________________
[1] Lewis Ayres, “On Not Three People: The Fundamental Themes of Gregory of Nyssa’s Trinitarian Theology as Seen in To Ablabius: On Not Three Gods,” Modern Theology 18, no. 4 (October 2002): 446.
[2] This letter, however, is not the broadest treatment of Gregory’s monarchia Trinitarian theology. Rather, it is an acute summary of his theology which under girds his response to Ablabius. See his Catechetical Orations 1–4.
[3] With the intentions of advancing a ecclesial response against the Arian claim that Christ was a created being, a sixth-century church council in Toledo, Spain, added the word filioque (and the Son) to a creed describing the procession of the Holy Spirit, thereby affirming that the Holy Spirit was sent by the Father and the Son (John 14:26; 15:26). The Eastern church objected to the addition, because it was a speculative move beyond what Scripture teaches about the Spirit. While there were other factors, this controversy initiated the formal Schism of 1054 between the Roman Catholic and Eastern Orthodox Churches. The debate pertains to the problem of affirming Jesus as the Source, equal to the Father, in sending the Spirit. Reason being, in order to be monotheists, there can only be one Source, who is the Father. If Jesus is the Source as the Father is, then we have two Gods. For an accessible summary of the filioque controversy, see Robert Letham, The Holy Trinity: In Scripture, History, Theology, and Worship (Phillipsburg, N.J: P&R Publishing, 2004), 201–20.
[4] Ayres, “On Not Three People,” 449.
[5] In a letter to his brother Peter, Gregory analyzes the terms ousia and hypostasis, providing the clearest understanding and use of these terms in the Cappadocians' theology. “Letter 35 To Peter His Own Brother on the Divine Ousia and Hypostasis (Ad Petrum 1)” in Anna M. Silvas, Gregory of Nyssa: The Letters: Introduction, Translation and Commentary, Gregory of Nyssa: The Letters (Brill, 2006).
[6] Ayres, “On Not Three People,” 450, 51.
[7] Ibid., 456.
[8] Ibid., 457.
[9] Ibid., 459.
[10] Ibid., 462.
[11] Ibid., 463.
Comments