Skip to main content

Boethius: The Logic of Unity and Plurality in One God

In the “Introduction” to a standard English translation of Boethius’ Theological Tractates and the Consolation of Philosophy, it is stated that “Boethius was the last of the Roman philosophers, and the first of the scholastic theologians” (X).  Philosophy is aimed at explaining the nature of the world (the natural). Theology’s aim is to understand and explain doctrines delivered by divine revelation (the supernatural). Boethius was the seminal figure in preparing the way for the synthesis of these two disciplines, with philosophy serving the task of theology (i.e., the handmaiden to the King of sciences).

Anicus Manlius Severinus Boethius was born around 480 AD in Rome to the famous Praenestine family of the Anicii. He followed in his father’s footsteps as a consul under Theodoric the Ostrogoth in 510, to then be charged by Theodoric with conspiracy and treasonous activity and was thrown into prison, where he died a brutal death in 524. While his life was short, his literary output was remarkable. He was astute and well-learned in the works of Plato and Aristotle. In prison he wrote his Consolation of Philosophy. He set the bar high for himself, with the hopes of translating all the works of Plato and Aristotle for his native countrymen. He produced major works of philosophy, along with arithmetic, music, and his five theological tractates that all stand on their own (x–xiv).

 

The texts under examination in our present study is Boethius’ treatises/letters, The Trinity in One God not Three Gods, and a shorter piece, a letter to John the Deacon, titled Whether Father, Son, and Holy Spirit May be Substantially Predicated of the Divinity. 


The Trinity in One God not Three Gods (De Trin.

As the title indicates, this treatise is Boethius’ attempt at discerning the mystery of the Trinity, specifically an articulation of how God is triune yet one. Jumping ahead a bit, Boethius intimates that “the category of substance preserves the Unity, that of relation brings about the Trinity” (De Trin., VI.29). Defining substance and relation within this construct will reveal the cogency of the Trinity doctrine (though still profoundly mysterious). And that is nature of the inquiry ahead.

Boethius begins the treatise with the utmost humility as he embarks on his study. He understands the task ahead of him will press him (and all mankind for that matter) to the height of human wit, deep into the heavenly knowledge, far beyond what human reason can reach. But he is going to apply the “unaccustomed words” and “deep questionings of philosophy” to his endeavor. However, because of the difficulty of the task, he requests leniency, while asking that the reader (his father-in-law) hold his claims up to the light of Augustine, who planted the seeds in his mind, which he hopes will bear fruit in his inquiry to follow.  

The universal article of belief in the Christian faith, “concerning the Unity of the Trinity is as follows: the Father is God, the Son is God, the Holy Spirit is God. Therefore Father, Son, and Holy Spirit are one God, not three Gods” (De Trin., I.7). Boethius begins his approach, considering the nature of the discipline in which he is operating. He notes that the three main branches of speculative science are physics, mathematics, and theology. Physics deals with motion, how “the forms of bodies together with their constituent matter are in motion.” Math doesn’t deal with motion nor is it abstract; rather, “it investigates forms of bodies apart from matter.” And “theology does not deal with motion, is abstract and separable, for the Divine Substance is without either matter or form” (De Trin., II.9).

So, in seeing the diversity of these sciences, theology operates in a plane of its own, a sui generis, to that of physics and math because the “Divine Substance is Form without matter, and is therefore One, and is its own essence.” Physics is bound to scientific inquiry, math, systematical, and theology, intellectual concepts. And the prima intellectual concept is simply that Form which is pure form and no image, is very Being and the source of Being (De Trin., II.9). We can see Boethius’ starting point is that of the simple essence of God, notably God is very Being and the source of Being. All other things have being from the Source, whereas God is very Being and is the source of his own Being.

Utilizing substance metaphysics, he notes what is proper to all created being, that “everything that exists owes its being to Form.” And he provides an elementary illustration to explain this notion; a statue is not a statue because of its material, its matter; rather, its form as a statue is due “to the likeness of a living thing impressed upon it.” Matter doesn’t qualify what something is; rather, it is was it is because of the distinctive form given to it. However, “the Divine Substance is Form without matter, and is therefore One, and is its own essence” (De Trin., II.11). We can see Boethius is setting out the categories of simple and composite, which God is the former and created being the latter. He writes, “But other things are not simply their own essences, for each thing has its being from the things which it is composed, that is from its parts.” To use a phrase coined by Aquinas, Boethius is expressing: all that is in God is God. Creatures are what they are because of the parts of which they are composed. God as simple essence, being his own essence, cannot be made up of parts otherwise the parts would be greater than the whole because the whole would depend on the parts, thus something prior to God would have to give him the parts to make God who he is.

Creatures consist of “This and That, i.e., it is the totality of its parts in conjunction; it is not This or That taken apart.” But God, however, “does not consist of This and That, but is only This, is really its own essence, and is altogether beautiful and stable because it is not grounded in anything” (De Trin., II.11). Boethius makes an interesting move, in that he observes that the entailment of God as his own essence, is that he “is truly One in which is no number, in which nothing is present except its own existence.” As Pure Form, God cannot be the substrate of anything, like a creature, which is a substrate for accidents. A substrateis a substance considered as a subject supporting its accidents, and accidents are properties (parts) added to a thing, or received by the substance, but are not inherent in the thing.

For example, a man’s hair is not what makes him a man, or human. Hair is an accident (or crudely put, an appendage) that is added to him. If a man doesn’t have hair, it doesn’t take his humanity away (his pride, maybe). So, in God, as Pure Form, he cannot have accidents (appendages), otherwise God would have parts; he would receive something that does not properly exist from himself. Pure Form doesn’t receive a property; it is the giver of all properties. Therefore, his attributes are not accidents; otherwise, as noted above, something apart from God would make God who he is, thus the parts would then be greater than the whole. Boethius concludes, “In Him, then, is no difference, no plurality arising out of difference, no multiplicity arising out of accidents, and accordingly no number” (De Trin., II.13).

Next, Boethius moves into a discussion regarding oneness, explaining how God doesn’t differ from God in any respect, even the three unities withing the oneness of God. Therefore, when we speak of the Father, the Son, and the Spirit, these three are not individuated divine essences. When it comes to oneness and pluralities, Boethius notes there are two manners of counting, abstract and concrete. Abstract counting does not produce a plurality of what we count; concrete counting is numbering that which is inherent in the thing counted (De Trin., III.13). “Oneness,” therefore, “is a thing—the thing counted. Unity is that by which oneness is denoted.” Boethius is setting up a distinction that allows us to recognize plurality of a thing within the oneness of that thing. So, when we speak of the unities of a thing, such as “one sword, one brand, and one blade,” the terms are merely repetitions denoting the one sword, “not a numbering of unities but simply repeating one thing” (De Trin., III.15). An abstract manner of counting produces plurality but concrete counting does not because things counted are each concrete unities of that which is being counted; therefore, counting the one thing concretely is to reiterate what it is, not enumerate several different things. The sun, for example, when we say sun three times we are merely mentioning it three times over, not three distinct suns.

Speaking of God, then, when we say Father, Son, and Spirit, “the threefold predication does not result in plural number.” And when we make this threefold predication, the things counted in the divine essence are not synonymous terms; rather, Boethius says they are reiterations of the one and the same thing (De Trin., III.15). In going back to the sword analogy, blade, brand, and sword are unique distinctions of the one thing, but each distinction speaks of the entirety of the whole thing itself. Therefore, in speaking of the Pure Form of God, concretely speaking, the Father is God completely, the Son is God completely, and the Spirit is God completely. However, the Father is not the same as the Son, nor the Son the Father, nor the Father the Spirit, nor the Spirit the Father, nor the Son the Spirit, nor the Spirit the Son.

Boethius is satisfied having established how the category of substance, as it pertains to the Pure Form (the divine essence), preserves its unity. But he needs to tease things out further. While there are categories that can be predicated of things universally[1] they cannot be predicated of God; rather, Boethius notes, when “applied to God they change their meaning entirely.” Reason being, substance in Him is not really substantial but supersubstantial” (De Trin., IV.17). And as we will see, this is because God is simple. What is it to be supersubstantial? God’s essence as supersubstantial is called as such because his essence is beyond subjection to accidents. So, what quality or property we speak of in God, it is in him supersubstantially. Therefore, Boethius writes:

For God is not one thing because He is, and another thing because He is just; with Him to be just and to be God are One and the same. So, when we say, “He is great or the greatest,” we seem to predicate quantity, but it is a quantity similar to this substance which we have declared to be supersubstantial; for with Him to be great and to be God are all one. (De Trin. IV. 19)

As simple divine essence or Pure Form, he is one without plurality of the divine being. Boethius qualifies the difference between God and man.  The distinction between God and man is that a man is not entirely man or all of humanity; therefore, a man is a man in virtue of receiving his being from that which is not man. A man cannot be called the substance of mankind, since humanity is a form, from which God brings into existence a man (composed of matter and form) as supposit, a substance that is complete in itself and is uncommunicated or unshared with another part or being. But, Boethius writes, “God is simply and entirely God, for He is nothing else than what He is, and therefore is, through simple existence, God” (De Trin., IV.19).

The distinction between God and man entails a different manner of understanding when predicating the attributes to each one. So, when we say man is just and God is just, to be just and to be man are different things, whereby just would be predicated of man in an accidental way; whereas, when we say God is just, God is justice itself. Likewise, to say a man is great is to say he has greatness, but when speaking of God, he is greatness itself.

Boethius continues, speaking of the other qualities or categories that pertain to a created thing in contrast to God. As to location, we can say a man is located somewhere, but we don’t predicate location of man according to his substance, as if we were to say a man is tall or short. Rather, when speaking of man’s location, we are predicating his substance in a particular setting in relation to other things. But, speaking of God, we cannot predicate location of the divine essence because it is a creaturely attribution. While we speak of the divine essence in such language, as in saying God is everywhere, because God is simple essence, Pure Form, no place can receive him, so, Boethius writes, “he cannot be anywhere in a place, since He is everywhere but in no place” (De Trin., IV.21).

As to time, man is here today, gone tomorrow; but “God is ever,” with ever denoting “a single Present, summing Up his continual presence in all the past, in all the present—however, that term be used—and in all the future” (De Trin., IV.21). The great distinction between creatures and God as it pertains to time, Boethius writes, is that “our present connotes changing time and sempiternity [i.e., never ending duration; everlasting]; God’s present, abiding, unmoved, and immoveable, connotes eternity” (De Trin., IV.21).  

Boethius moves through other categories, noting distinctions of predication when speaking of God and man. His ultimate end is to demonstrate that while these “categories describe a thing in terms of its substance [i.e., created things], they are called substantial categories and when applied to things as subjects, they are called accidents.” However, since “God is not a subject at all, it is only possible to employ the category of substance” (De Trin., IV.25).

Being satisfied in demonstrating that the unity of God is preserved according to the category of substance, Boethius considers the category of relation to bring out the Trinity. The term relation doesn’t pertain to the essence of a thing; rather, it only describes the thing in relation to another, that is, in opposition to another (but not in a combative sense). For example, two men standing next to each other said to be in relation to one another. But that relation is not essential; rather, it depends on the subjects in opposition to each other. Relation is not a qualitative or substantial change in the essence or nature of the subjects (i.e., the two men). The category of relation allows us to make real distinctions between two subjects without requiring difference, change, or alteration of their nature in any way. With that understanding of relation in mind, Boethius writes,

Wherefore, if Father and Son are predicates of relation, and, as we have said, have no other difference but that of relation, and if relation is not asserted of its subject as though it were the subject itself and its substantial quality, it will effect no real difference in its subject, but, in a phrase which aims at interpreting what we can hardly understand, a difference of persons. (De Trin., V.27).

Beothius makes this claim because that which is incorporeal can only be distinct from another thing by differences not spatial location. Because God is pure essence, having no change or addition to his being, he wasn’t at one time God and then Father was added to his substance; rather, he is ever Father. And the Son, ever Son, thus the Father’s begetting of the Son belongs to his very substance. But, and this is key to retaining the unity of the Triunity, we predicate the Father as Father in relation to the Son. Because God is Pure Form, simple essence, thus incorporeal, the essence of God cannot be spatially different, thus Father, Son, and the Holy Spirit can only be distinct according to relation (De Trin., V.27).

In articulating the essence of God in this manner, we can say there are no differences (i.e., spatial distinctions or locations) in God, thus no plurality and because there is no plurality there is Unity. How is this so? God is God through Godself, and “in concrete enumerations the repetition of the units does not produce plurality. Thus, the Unity of the Three is suitably established” (De Trin., V.29).

The logic of the Trinity, whereby the Christian God is One not three gods, is that the relation (i.e., the distinctions between the Divine Persons) secures the Trinity because the category of relation brings about no substantial change or alteration of the one, simple divine essence, thus maintaining the unity of the Triune God. Succinctly put, “the category of substance preserves the Unity, that of relation brings about the Trinity” (De Trin., VI.29). And because the simple essence is One, and all three persons have the One essence, whatever we predicate of one of the Persons (i.e., goodness, justice, greatness, etc.) is the same in all the other persons. However, when we do predicate one of these truths, we do not say there are three truths; that would divide the divine essence; “the one substance of the Three, cannot be separated or divided, nor is it made up of various parts, combined into one: it is simply one” (De Trin., VI.33, 35).  


Conclusion

In this short, yet substantial treatise, Boethius’ investigation into the nature of the One, Triune God, provides for us a cogent, faithful articulation of the Trinity. His final words in closing reveal what a proper approach in discerning the mystery of the pure essence of the One God should lead us to: “joyous praise.” True theology should be doxological because that is the endeavor of doing theology. Boethius writes,

If, God helping me, I have furnished some support in argument to an article which stands by itself on the firm foundation of Faith, I shall render joyous praise for the finished work to Him from whom the invitation comes. But if human nature has failed to reach beyond its limits, whatever is lost through my infirmity must be made good by my intention. (De Trin., VI.31).


~ Romans 11:36 ~
 

[1] Boethius is referring to Substance, Quality, Quantity, Relation, Place, Time, Condition, Situation, Activity, and Passivity. These ten categories only apply to contingent things; God is uncreated, therefore, none of these categories can be predicated properly of God.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Gregory of Nyssa: Trinity–Not Tri-deity

Gregory, a bishop of Nyssa in 371, was part of the Cappadocian trio, and was instrumental in the development of Trinitarian orthodoxy. His theological prowess proved vital in response to the Arian and Sabellian heresies. Key to Gregory’s theology we find “an emergence of a pro-Nicene ‘grammar’ of divinity through his developed account of divine power,” [1] conceived through a nature-power-activity formulation revealed in the created order and articulated in Scripture. Understanding the Triune God in this manner afforded a conception of the Trinity that was logical and thoroughly biblical. And this letter is paradigmatic on Gregory’s account of the divine nature. (* This article was later published with Credo Magazine, titled, “ The Grammar of Divinity (On Theology). ” See link below) To Ablabius, though short, is a polemical address whereby Gregory lays out a complex argument in response to the claim that three Divine Persons equal three gods. Basically put, Ablabius (his opponent,...

St. John Chrysostom — for God is simple

Below is part of the introductory section to my exposition of John Chrysostom’s doctrine of God. I posted it because I thought it was fascinating to find such an important theologian known for avoiding (even having a disdain of) speculative theology refer to the classical doctrine of divine simplicity as common place in his thoroughly biblical doctrine of God. Toward the end I include a link to my full exposition. John Chrysostom (ca. 347–407) was the archbishop of Constantinople. Being the most prolific of all the Eastern fathers, he fought against the ecclesiastical and political leaders for their abuse of authority. He was called Chrysostom (meaning “golden-mouthed”) for his eloquent sermons. [1] This most distinguished of Greek patristic preachers excelled in spiritual and moral application in the Antiochene tradition of literal exegesis, largely disinterested, even untutored in speculative and controversial theology. [2] On the Incomprehensible Nature of G...

Clement of Alexandria: Nuances of the Classical God

Clement of Alexandria (c. 150–c. 215) was the head of the Catechetical School of Alexandria (c. 190), and the teacher of Origen. Concerned that Christianity is not seen as an unsophisticated religion, Clement sought to reconcile his faith with the best of Greek philosophy, specifically in the usefulness of Middle Platonism.[1] He believed that the kernels of truth found in Plato and Greek Philosophy were preparatory for the Gentiles in leading them to Christ, just as the Law was a guide or guardian for the Hebrews. Clement’s esoteric exegesis and speculative theology emphasized a higher knowledge, but this knowledge was obtained only through the Logos.

John 17:3 – Eternal Life is Knowing God and Christ–the One, True God

    John 17:1–5. “ Jesus spoke these things, looked up to heaven, and said, “Father, the hour has come. Glorify your Son so that the Son may glorify you, since you gave him authority over all people, so that he may give eternal life to everyone you have given him. This is eternal life: that they may know you, the only true God, and the one you have sent—Jesus Christ. I have glorified you on the earth by completing the work you gave me to do. Now, Father, glorify me in your presence with that glory I had with you before the world existed .”

Gregory of Nazianzus: The Trinity - Not a Collection of Elements

Gregory of Nazianzus   One of the Cappadocian fathers, Gregory of Nazianzus (c.330–389), given the title, “The Theologian,” was instrumental in the development of the doctrine of the Trinity, specifically the distinct terms to describe the Persons of the Godhead (Unbegotten, eternally begotten, and procession). Gregory’s main contribution to the development of Christology was in his opposition to Apollinarius. He argued that when Adam fell, all of humanity fell in him; therefore, that fallen nature must be fully united to the Son—body, soul, and mind; ‘for the unassumed is the unhealed’.   Gregory’s Doctrine of the Trinity His clearest statement on the Trinity is found in his Oration 25.15–18. Oration 25 is part of a series of sermons delivered in 380. As a gesture of gratitude, Gregory dedicates Oration 25 to Christian philosopher Maximus the Cynic, as a sort of ‘charge’ for him to push forward and remain strong in the orthodox teachings of the faith. And these sections ar...

A Brief Exposition of Augustine's Doctrine of Divine Immutability

To much of the Western world, Augustine has no rival. He is the preeminent—uninspired—theologian of the Christian faith. When reading the titans of the church—i.e., Aquinas, Luther, and Calvin—Augustine’s theology and ideas are voluminously parroted all throughout their writings. His influence is unparalleled. Even the secular world sees Augustine as a mammoth figure in the shaping of human history. And its Augustine’s doctrine of God we will divert our attention to, looking specifically at his articulation of divine immutability Augustine’s doctrine of God is classical, through and through. He writes, “There is One invisible, from whom, as the Creator and First Cause, all things seen by us derive their being: He is supreme, eternal, unchangeable, and comprehensible by none save Himself alone” ( Ep . 232.5).[1] When reading his works, the doctrine of immutability is paramount, coming forth repeatedly. For Augustine, immutability, or God’s unchangeableness, is consequential ...

“A New Heaven and New Earth” ~ A (Partial) Preterist Reading of Isaiah 65:17–25

When God says he will create a new heaven and a new earth, what will this new heaven and earth be like? Is it describing an obliteration of the material world, with a new material heaven and earth to follow? Early Church Father Jerome did not see a destruction of the elements; instead, he saw newness , a change into something better. Commenting on this passage, he writes, “The Apostle Paul said, ‘for the form of this world is perishing’ [1Co 7:31]. Notice that he said ‘form,’ not ‘substance.’”[1] Thomas Aquinas sees the new heavens and earth to be “the restoration of goods, for behold I create a new heavens , with new help from heaven, and a new earth , new benefits from the earth; this refers to the day of judgment, when the world will be renewed to the glory of the saints: the former things have passed away (Re 21:4).”[2] Closer to the immediate historical context, another understanding sees this as “a hyperbolic expression of the future restoration of the people of Judah after the ...

Isaiah 45:7 - “ . . . I make peace, and create evil.” — Does God create evil?

My daughter watched a video this morning where a deconstructionist, an ex vangelical, was attempting to profane the goodness of God, by pointing out that Isaiah 45:7 says God creates evil. She was referring to the KJV version of this passage which says, “I form the light, and create darkness: I make peace, and create evil: I the LORD do all these things.” So, what do we do with that? Below is a brief response. Proper biblical interpretation considers context when seeking the meaning of a passage. Furthermore, when it comes to difficult or obscure passages, a helpful rule of interpretation is to look to the plainer passages of the Bible and draw examples from them to shed light on the more obscure passages ( thanks Augustine ). We let Scripture interpret Scripture. The point is to remove all hesitation on doubtful passages. So, in this passage, on the face it seems to imply that God creates evil, thus making God evil. But is that what the Bible teaches about God? The plainer passages te...

Origen: How is the Son the Invisible Image of the Invisible God?

Early Church Father Origen of Alexandria (c. 185–c. 254), considered the “greatest theological luminary of his age,” [1] his prolific writings amassed to some six thousand works. While his exegetical contribution to the formulation of Christian doctrine greatly shaped the theology of the fourth century, he is also a controversial fellow. Nevertheless, it is important that when we read such figures writing theology in the nascent stages of the Christian Faith, we must do our best to keep them in their context—to prevent hasty anathematizing. We have the privilege of 1900 years of theological development to stand on, passed on to us through toil, tears, and even death. Anyway...   I have been studying Origen’s writings, particularly his First Principles ( De Principiis) , and came across a wonderful insight that illuminated my thinking on Christ as the image of God. I am working on a doctrine of God course. Below is an excerpt from my lecture material. So, we are going to drop rig...

Athanasius: Divine Simplicity as True Existence

Early Church Father, Athanasius (c. 296–373) Bishop of Alexandria (Egypt) was a giant figure in the advancement and preservation of orthodox Christianity. He labored more than anyone to bring about the triumph of the orthodox Nicene faith over Arianism, which promoted the view that Christ, though glorious and supreme, was a created being. Athanasius’ consistent tenacity in defending the full deity of Christ spanned forty-five years over which he was exiled five times. But his efforts kept the Orthodox faith from being eclipsed by Arian cohorts. As I have been reading through his works, in preparation for a class on the essence and attributes of God, I have been paying close attention the doctrine of divine simplicity. And so, the body of this essay will be an exposition of Athanasius’ views on simplicity from his treatise Contra Gentes ( Against the Heathens ). In this treatise, Athanasius establishes Christian theism against the pantheistic philosophies that the heathens held. Panthe...